twitter

Saturday 14 July 2018

Is There Progress in Philosophy? The Case for Taking History Seriously

Peter P. Slezak https://doi.org/10.1017/S0031819118000232Published online: 29 June 2018 Abstract In response to widespread doubts among professional philosophers (Russell, Horwich, Dietrich, McGinn, Chalmers), Stoljar argues for a ‘reasonable optimism’ about progress in philosophy. He defends the large and surprising claim that ‘there is progress on all or reasonably many of the big questions’. However, Stoljar's caveats and admitted avoidance of historical evidence permits overlooking persistent controversies in philosophy of mind and cognitive science that are essentially unchanged since the 17th Century. Stoljar suggests that his claims are commonplace in philosophy departments and, indeed, the evidence I adduce constitutes an indictment of the widely shared view among professional analytic philosophers. Export citation Copyright COPYRIGHT: © The Royal Institute of Philosophy 2018 Footnotes Hide All I am grateful to Daniel Stoljar and David Chalmers for very helpful comments on an earlier version of this paper. Thanks also to Galen Strawson for helpful remarks on the themes of this paper. References Hide All 2 Stoljar, D., Philosophical Progress: In Defence of a Reasonable Optimism (Oxford University Press, 2017), 165 CrossRef | Google Scholar. 3 Horwich, P., Wittgenstein's Metaphilosophy (Oxford University Press, 2012), 34 CrossRef | Google Scholar. 4 Strawson, G., ‘Panpsychism?’ in Freeman, A. (ed.) Consciousness and its Place in Nature (Exeter: Imprint Academic Press, 2006), 184 Google Scholar. 5 Rescher, N., Philosophical Progress and Other Philosophical Studies (De Gruyter, 2014) Google Scholar. 6 Chalmers, D.J., ‘Why Isn't There More Progress in Philosophy?’, Philosophy 90 (2015): 3–31 CrossRef | Google Scholar. 7 Dietrich, E., ‘There Is No Progress in Philosophy’, Essays in Philosophy 12/2 (2011): 329–44 Google Scholar. To take a significant example, there is, after all, a wide ‘collective convergence’ among philosophers on Kripke's views of naming which are ‘as close to uncontroversial as any interesting views in analytic philosophy’ according to Christopher Hughes. Michael Devitt, too, notes ‘We can probably assume that nearly all philosophers of language agree with Kripkean intuitions’ on the conception of rigid designators taken to refute the Russell-Frege descriptivist account of names. See Hughes, C., Kripke: Names, Necessity and Identity (Oxford: Clarendon Press, 2004), vii Google Scholar; Devitt, M., ‘Whither Experimental Semantics?’ Theoria 72 (2011): 5–36, 24 Google Scholar. For a dissenting view, see Chomsky, N., ‘Language and Interpretation: Philosophical Reflections and Empirical Inquiry’ in Earman, J. (ed.) Inference, Explanation, and Other Frustrations (Berkeley: University of California Press, 1992), 99–128 Google Scholar; Chomsky, N., The Science of Language: Interviews with James McGilvray (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 2012), 28 CrossRef | Google Scholar. 8 Kuhn, T.S., The Structure of Scientific Revolutions (University of Chicago Press, 1962) Google Scholar. 9 Laudan, L., Progress and its Problems (University of California Press, 1977) Google Scholar. 10 Stoljar op. cit. note 2 (2017), 14. 11 Russell, B., The Problems of Philosophy (Oxford University Press, 1912/1967) Google Scholar. 12 Wittgenstein, L., Tractatus Logico-Philosophicus (Routledge & Kegan Paul, 1922), 5 Google Scholar. 13 Schlick, M., ‘The Turning Point in Philosophy’ (1930), in Ayer, A.J. (ed.) Logical Positivism (The Free Press, 1959): 53–59 Google Scholar. 14 Stoljar op. cit. note 2 (2017), x. 15 I neglect consideration of Stoljar's apparatus of ‘boundary problems’, ‘constitutive’ and ‘successor’ problems since we may concede Stoljar's positive arguments for progress in certain narrowly specified respects. I am concerned to reveal what has been left out of account in judging the state of the discipline. 16 Stoljar op. cit. note 2 (2017), x. 17 Stoljar op. cit. note 2 (2017), 77. 18 Chalmers op. cit. note 6 (2015), 25. 19 Stoljar op. cit. note 2 (2017), 143. 20 Stoljar op. cit. note 2 (2017), 147. 21 Gettier, E.L., ‘Is Justified True Belief Knowledge?’, Analysis 23 (1963): 121–3 CrossRef | Google Scholar. 22 Nozick, R., ‘Newcomb's Problem and Two Principles of Choice’, in Rescher, N. et al. (eds) Essays in Honor of Carl G. Hempel (Dordrecht: D. Reidel, 1969) Google Scholar. 23 Quoted in Lycan, W.G., ‘On the Gettier Problem Problem’ in Hetherington, S. (ed.) Epistemology Futures, (Oxford: Clarendon Press, 2006), 148 Google Scholar. 24 On Gettier see Kirkham, R.L., ‘Does the Gettier Problem Rest on a Mistake?’, Mind 93 (1984): 501–513 CrossRef | Google Scholar; Zagzebski, L., ‘The Inescapability of Gettier Problems’, Philosophical Quarterly 44 (1994): 65–73 CrossRef | Google Scholar; and Hetherington, S., ‘The Gettier Illusion’, Synthese 188 (2012): 217–230 CrossRef | Google Scholar. 25 Curley, E.M., ‘Dialogues with the Dead’, Synthese 67 (1986): 33–49, 37 CrossRef | Google Scholar. 26 Quine, W.V.O., The Time of My Life (Cambridge, Mass.: MIT Press, 1985), 194 Google Scholar. 27 Gaukroger, S., Descartes: An Intellectual Biography (Oxford: Oxford University Press, 1996), 8 Google Scholar. 28 Pasnau, R., Theories of Cognition in the Later Middle Ages (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1997), 294 Google Scholar. 29 Stoljar op. cit. note 2 (2017), 125. 30 Quoted in E.M. Curley op. cit. note 24. See also Wilson, C., ‘Is the History of Philosophy Good for Philosophy?’ in Sorell, T. and Rogers, G.A.J. (eds) Analytic Philosophy and History of Philosophy (Oxford: Clarendon Press, 2005), 75 Google Scholar. 31 Stoljar op. cit. note 2 (2017), 12, 58. 32 Levine, J., ‘Materialism and qualia: the explanatory gap’, Pacific Philosophical Quarterly 64 (1983): 354–61 CrossRef | Google Scholar. 33 Fodor, J.A., ‘Don't bet the chicken coop’, London Review of Books 24 (2001): 21–22 Google Scholar. 34 McGinn, C., ‘Consciousness and Cosmology: Hyperdualism Ventilated’ in Davies, M. and Humphreys, G.W. (eds) Consciousness (Oxford: Blackwell, 1993), 157 Google Scholar. 35 Strawson, G., Consciousness and its Place in Nature (Exeter: Imprint Academic, 2006), 15 Google Scholar. 36 Chalmers, D., The Conscious Mind: In Search of a Fundamental Theory (Oxford: Oxford University Press, 1996), xi Google Scholar. 37 Sorell, T., ‘On Saying No to History of Philosophy’ in Sorell, T. and Rogers, G.A.J. (eds) Analytic Philosophy and History of Philosophy (Oxford: Clarendon, 2005), 1 Google Scholar. 38 Wilson, M.D., ‘History of Philosophy in Philosophy Today; and the Case of the Sensible Qualities’ in Ideas and Mechanisms: Essays on Early Modern Philosophy (Princeton: Princeton University Press, 1999), 459 CrossRef | Google Scholar. 39 Strawson op. cit. note 35 (2006), 201. 40 Nadler, S., ‘Reid, Arnauld and the Objects of Perception’, History of Philosophy Quarterly 3 (1986): 165–173, 104 Google Scholar. 41 Clarke, D.M., Descartes's Theory of Mind (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 2003) CrossRef | Google Scholar. 42 Dennett, D.C., Consciousness Explained (London: Penguin, 1991) Google Scholar. 43 Pylyshyn, Z., Seeing and Visualizing: It's Not What You Think (Cambridge, Mass.: MIT Press, 2003) Google Scholar; Pylyshyn, Z., ‘Return of the mental image: are there really pictures in the brain?’, Trends in Cognitive Science 7 (2003): 113–118 CrossRef | Google Scholar. 44 Clarke, D. M., Descartes’ Philosophy of Science (Manchester: Manchester University Press, 1982), 2 Google Scholar. 45 D. M. Clarke op. cit. note 41 (2003), 258. 46 Koyré, A., ‘Introduction’, Anscombe, E. & Geach, P.T. (eds) Descartes: Philosophical Writings (Middlesex: Thomas Nelson, 1954), vii Google Scholar. 47 For example, recent book-length treatments include: Sarkar, H., Descartes’ Cogito (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 2003) CrossRef | Google Scholar; Broughton, J., Descartes's Method of Doubt (Princeton: Princeton University Press, 2002) Google Scholar; Baker, G. & Morris, K.J., Descartes’ Dualism (London: Routledge, 1996) Google Scholar; Rozemond, M., Descartes's Dualism (Cambridge, Mass.: Harvard University Press, 1998) Google Scholar. 48 Smith, D. Woodruff, ‘The Cogito circa AD 2000’, Inquiry 36 (2000): 225–54 CrossRef | Google Scholar. 49 Hintikka, J., ‘Cogito Ergo Sum: Inference or Performance?’, The Philosophical Review 71 (1962): 3–32 CrossRef | Google Scholar. 50 Frankfurt, H., Demons, Dreamers, and Madmen: The Defense of Reason in Descartes's Meditation (New York: Bobbs-Merrill, 1970 Google Scholar; republished by Princeton University Press, 2008), 15. 51 Cottingham, J., ‘Why Should Analytic Philosophers Do History of Philosophy’ in Sorell, T. and Rogers, G.A.J. (eds) Analytic Philosophy and History of Philosophy (Oxford: Clarendon Press, 2005), vii Google Scholar. 52 Chalmers op. cit. note 6 (2015). 53 Bar-Hillel, Y., ‘Indexical Expressions’, Aspects of Language (Jerusalem: Magnes Press, 1970), 199 Google Scholar. 54 Slezak, P., ‘Descartes's Diagonal Deduction’ British Journal for the Philosophy of Science 34 (1983): 13–36 CrossRef | Google Scholar; Slezak, P., ‘Was Descartes a Liar? Diagonal Doubt Defended’, British Journal for the Philosophy of Science 39 (1988): 379–388 CrossRef | Google Scholar; Slezak, P, ‘Doubts about Descartes’ Indubitability: The Cogito as Intuition & Inference’, Philosophical Forum 41 (2010): 389–412 CrossRef | Google Scholar. 55 Hintikka, J., ‘René pense, donc Cartesius existe’ Cahiers de philosophy de l'université de Caen 50 (2013): 107–120 Google Scholar. For acknowledgement of Hintikka's indebtedness, see Kieft, X., ‘Peter Slezak, interlocuteur anonyme de Jaakko Hintikka’, Bulletin cartésien XLIV, Archives de Philosophie 78 (2015): 157–216 Google Scholar. 56 Searle, J., ‘Minds, Brains and Programs’, Behavioral and Brain Sciences 3 (1980): 417–424 CrossRef | Google Scholar. See articles in Preston, J., and Bishop, M. (eds) Views Into the Chinese Room: New Essays on Searle and Artificial Intelligence (Oxford: Clarendon Press, 2002) Google Scholar. 57 Descartes, R., Optics. The Writings on Descartes, Volume 1. Cottingham, J., Stoothoff, R. & Murdoch, Dugald, translators (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1985), 166 Google Scholar. 58 Quoted in Yolton, J.W., Perceptual Acquaintance from Descartes to Reid (Minneapolis: University of Minnesota Press, 1984), 28 Google Scholar. 59 Tye, M., The Imagery Debate (Cambridge, Mass., MIT Press, 1991) Google Scholar. 60 Rorty, R., Philosophy and the Mirror of Nature (Princeton: Princeton University Press, 1979), 146 Google Scholar. 61 Block, N., ‘Introduction: What is the issue?’ in Block, N. (ed.) Imagery. (Cambridge, Mass.: MIT Press, 1981), 1 Google Scholar. 62 Pylyshyn op. cit. note 43 (2003). 63 Schmaltz, T.M., ‘Malebranche on Ideas and the Vision in God’ in Nadler, S. (ed.) The Cambridge Companion to Malebranche (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 2000), 73 Google Scholar. 64 Descartes op. cit. note 57, 165. 65 Jackson, F., ‘Epiphenomenal Qualia’ Philosophical Quarterly 32 (1982): 127–136 CrossRef | Google Scholar; reprinted in Ludlow, P., Nagasawa, U. and Stoljar, D. (eds) There's Something About Mary, (Cambridge, Mass.: MIT Press, 2004) Google Scholar. 66 Jackson, F., ‘The Knowledge Argument, Diaphanousness, Representationalism’ in Alter, T. and Walter, S. (eds) Phenomenal Concepts and Phenomenal Knowledge: New Essays on Consciousness and Physicalism, (Oxford: Oxford University Press, 2007), 54 Google Scholar. 67 Schmaltz, T.M., Malebranche's Theory of the Soul: A Cartesian Interpretation, (Oxford: Oxford University Press, 1996), 85 Google Scholar. 68 Malebranche, N., The Search After Truth (1674), translated by Lennon, T.M. and Olscamp, P.J., (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1997), 634 Google Scholar. I am grateful to Tad Schmaltz for very helpful discussion of this issue. 69 Austin, J.L., Sense and Sensibilia (Oxford: Oxford University Press, 1962), 61 Google Scholar. 70 Locke, J., An Essay Concerning Human Understanding (1689) (ed.) Nidditch, P. H.. (Oxford: Oxford University Press, 1975), 424 Google Scholar. 71 Rorty op. cit. note 60 (1979). 72 Pasnau, R., Theories of Cognition in the Later Middle Ages (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1997), 5 Google Scholar. 73 Levine op. cit. note 32 (1983). 74 Nagel, T., ‘What is it like to be a bat?’, Philosophical Review 83 (1974): 435–450 CrossRef | Google Scholar. 75 Searle, J., The Mystery of Consciousness (London: Granta Books, 1997), 99 Google Scholar. 76 Sherrington, C., Man On His Nature (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1942) Google Scholar. 77 Dennett, D.C., ‘Illusionism as the Obvious Default Theory of Consciousness’, Journal of Consciousness Studies 23 (2016): 65–72 Google Scholar, 70. 78 Place, U.T., ‘Is Consciousness a Brain Process?’, British Journal of Psychology 47 (1956): 44–50 CrossRef | Google Scholar | PubMed. reprinted in Beakley, B. and Ludlow, P. (eds) The Philosophy of Mind: Classical Problems/Contemporary Issues (Cambridge, Mass.: Bradford/MIT Press, 1992), 33–39 Google Scholar. 79 McGinn, C., ‘Can We Solve the Mind-Body Problem?’, Mind 98 (1989): 349–66 CrossRef | Google Scholar. 80 Quoted in Sutton, J., Philosophy and Memory Traces: Descartes to Connectionism (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1998), 119 Google Scholar. 81 Lycan, W.G., ‘Perspectival Representation and the Knowledge Argument’ in Smith, Q. and Jokic, A. (eds) Consciousness: New Philosophical Essays, (Oxford: Oxford University Press, 2003), 384 Google Scholar. 82 Rey, G., ‘Intentional Content and a Chomskian Linguistics’ in Barber, A. (ed.) Epistemology of Language (Oxford: Oxford University Press, 2003), 140 Google Scholar. 83 Cummins, R., Representations, Targets and Attitudes (Cambridge, MA: MIT Press, 1996), 1 Google Scholar. 84 Yolton, J.W., Perception and Reality: A History from Descartes to Kant, (Ithaca: Cornell University Press, 1996), 1 Google Scholar. 85 Fodor, J.A., Concepts: Where Cognitive Science Went Wrong (Oxford: Oxford University Press, 1998), 157 CrossRef | Google Scholar. 86 Yolton, J.W., Perceptual Acquaintance from Descartes to Reid (Minneapolis: University of Minnesota Press, 1984), 6 Google Scholar. 87 Fodor op.cit. note 85 and Fodor, J.A., Hume Variations (Oxford: Oxford University Press, 2003) Google Scholar. 88 See Pasnau op cit. note 28 (1997). 89 Moreau, D., Malebranche (Paris: Vrin, 2004), 89 Google Scholar. 90 Descartes, R., The Writings on Descartes, Volume II, Cottingham, J., Stoothoff, R. & Murdoch, Dugald, translators (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1984), 28 Google Scholar. 91 Block, N., ‘Advertisement for a Semantics for Psychology’ Midwest Studies in Philosophy, (Minneapolis: University of Minnesota Press, 1986) Google Scholar. Reprinted in Stich, S. and Warfield, T.A. (eds) Mental Representation: A Reader (Oxford: Blackwell, 1994): 81–141 Google Scholar. 92 Quoted in Watson, R.A., The Breakdown of Cartesian Metaphysics (Indianapolis: Hackett Publishing Company, 1987), 93 Google Scholar. 93 Fodor, J.A., ‘Presentation to the National Science Foundation Workshop on Information and Representation’ Partee, B.H., Peters, S. and Thomason, R. (eds) Report of Workshop on Information and Representation, (Washington, D.C.: NSF System Development Foundation, 1985), 106–117 Google Scholar. 94 Fodor, J.A., ‘Tom Swift and his Procedural Grandmother’ in his Representations: Philosophical Essays on the Foundations of Cognitive Science (Cambridge, Mass.: The MIT Press, 1981), 207 Google Scholar. 95 Searle op. cit. note 56 (1980). 96 Jackendoff, R., Languages of the Mind (Cambridge, Mass.: Bradford/MIT Press, 1992), 61 Google Scholar. 97 Fodor complains against ‘internalist’ semantics in generative linguistics that it is ‘In effect, … a sort of idealism about meaning: all our ideas are about ideas’. See Fodor, J.A., ‘Semantics: an interview’, Revista Virtual de Estudios da Linguagem 5 (2007): 6. Google Scholar Elsewhere, too, Fodor remarks ‘I don't understand how a semantics can avoid lapsing into idealistic solipsism unless it recognizes some sort of symbol-world relation.’ Fodor, J.A., LOT2: The Language of Thought Revisited (Oxford: Oxford University Press, 2008), 53 CrossRef | Google Scholar. 98 Locke, J. (1823), ‘An Examination of P. Malebranche's Opinion of Seeing All Things in God’, The Works of John Locke, A New Edition, Corrected, In Ten Volumes, Vol. IX. (London: Thomas Tegg; reprinted Amsterdam: Scientia Verlag Aalen, 1963) Google Scholar. 99 Nadler, S., Malebranche and Ideas (Oxford: Oxford University Press, 1992) Google Scholar. 100 Danto, A.C., Connections to the World: The Basic Concepts of Philosophy (New York: Harper & Row, 1989), xi Google Scholar. 101 Arnauld, A., On True and False Ideas (1963), translated with Introductory Essay by Stephen Gaukroger (Manchester: Manchester University Press, 1990), 63 Google Scholar. 102 See Tye, M., ‘The Adverbial Approach to Visual Experience’, The Philosophical Review 93 (1984): 195–225 CrossRef | Google Scholar. 103 Nadler op. cit. note 40 (1986), 166. 104 Van Cleve, J., Problems from Reid (Oxford: Oxford University Press, 2015), 67 Google Scholar. 105 Stoljar op. cit. note 2 (2017), 64. 106 von Eckardt, B., What Is Cognitive Science (Cambridge, Mass.: Bradford/MIT Press, 1993) Google Scholar. 107 von Eckardt op. cit. note 105, 145. See also Slezak, P., ‘The Tripartite Model of Representation’, Philosophical Psychology 15 (2002): 239–270 CrossRef | Google Scholar. 108 Bechtel, W., ‘Representations and Cognitive Explanations: Assessing the Dynamicists’ Challenge in Cognitive Science’ Cognitive Science 22 (1998): 295–318, 299 CrossRef | Google Scholar. 109 von Eckardt op. cit. note 106, 32. 110 Pylyshyn, Z., ‘The Imagery Debate: Analog Media versus Tacit Knowledge’, Psychological Review 88 (1981): 16–45 CrossRef | Google Scholar, reprinted in N. Block (ed.), Imagery (Cambridge, MA: Bradford/MIT Press, 1981); Pylyshyn, Z., Seeing and Visualizing: It's Not What You Think. (Cambridge, Mass.: MIT, 2003) Google Scholar. See also Slezak, P., ‘The Imagery Debate: Déjà vu all over again? Commentary on Zenon Pylyshyn’, Behavioral and Brain Sciences 25 (2002): 209–210 CrossRef | Google Scholar. 111 Schmaltz op. cit. note 63 (2000), 73. 112 Arnauld op. cit. note 101 (1683), 77. 113 Gelder, T. van, ‘The Dynamical Hypothesis in Cognitive Science’, Behavioral & Brain Sciences 21 (1998): 615–665 Google Scholar | PubMed; Bechtel op. cit. note 108 (1998). 114 See Clancey, W.J., ‘Situated Action’, Cognitive Science 17 (1993): 87–116 CrossRef | Google Scholar; Greeno, J.G., ‘Situations, Mental Models and Generative Knowledge’ in Klahr, D. and Kotovsky, K. (eds) Complex Information Processing: The Impact of Herbert A. Simon (New Jersey: Erlbaum, 1989) Google Scholar. 115 Nadler, S., Arnauld and the Cartesian Philosophy of Ideas (Manchester: Manchester University Press, 1989), 6 Google Scholar. 116 Fodor, J.A., ‘A Science of Tuesdays’ London Review of Books 22 (2000): 21–22 Google Scholar. 117 De Rosa, R., Descartes and the Puzzle of Sensory Representation, (Oxford: Oxford University Press, 2010), 13 CrossRef | Google Scholar. 118 Arnauld op. cit. note 101 (1683), 77. See Nadler op. cit. note 115 (1989), 97. 119 Putnam, H., ‘Sense, Nonsense, and the Senses: An Inquiry Into the Powers of the Human Mind’, The Journal of Philosophy 41 (1994): 445–517 CrossRef | Google Scholar, reprinted as The Threefold Cord: Mind, Body and World, (New York: Columbia University Press, 2000). 120 Fodor op. cit. note 116 (2000). 121 Copenhaver, R., ‘A Realism for Reid: Mediated But Direct’, British Journal for the History of Philosophy 12 (2004): 61–74 CrossRef | Google Scholar, 62. 122 Reid, T. (1813), Essays on the Intellectual Powers of Man, reproduced with Introduction by Brody, B. (Cambridge, Mass.: MIT Press, 1969), 161 Google Scholar. 123 Copenhaver op. cit. note 121 (2004), 72. 124 Fodor op. cit. note 87 (2003), 134. 125 Buckle, S., Hume's Enlightenment Tract (Oxford: Oxford University Press, 2001), 191 Google Scholar. 126 T.M. Lennon, ‘Introduction to N. Malebranche The Search After Truth’, translated by T.M. Lennon and P.J. Olscamp, (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1997), xxii. 127 Quoted in Buckle op. cit. note 124 (2001), 136. 128 See Jolley, N., The Light of the Soul: Theories of ideas in Leibniz, Malebranche, and Descartes (Oxford: Clarendon Press, 1990), 201 Google Scholar. 129 Fodor op. cit. note 97 (2007). 130 Fodor, J.A., ‘Review Essay: Remnants of Meaning by Stephen Schiffer’, Philosophy and Phenomenological Research 50 (1989): 409–423 CrossRef | Google Scholar, 409. 131 Yolton op. cit. note 84 (1996), 28. 132 Fodor op. cit. note 87 (2003), 135. 133 Fodor op. cit. note 85 (1998), 10. 134 Fodor, J.A., The Elm and the Expert: Mentalese and its Semantics (Cambridge, Mass.: MIT Press, 1994), 9 Google Scholar. 135 Fodor op. cit. note 87 (2003), 109. 136 Dretske, F., ‘Misrepresentation’ in Bogdan, R.J. (ed.) Belief: Form, Content and Function (Oxford: Oxford University Press, 1986) Google Scholar, reprinted in Stich, S. & Warfield, T. (eds) Mental Representation. (Oxford: Blackwell, 1994), 157–173 Google Scholar. Fodor, J.A., Psychosemantics: The Problem of Meaning in the Philosophy of Mind, (Cambridge, Mass.: MIT Press, 1987) Google Scholar; Fodor op. cit. note 133 (1994). 137 Fodor op. cit. note 116 (2000), 21. 138 Malebranche op. cit. note 68 (1674), 217. 139 Malebranche op. cit. note 68 (1674), 217. 140 Fodor op. cit. note 134 (1994), 83. 141 Curley op. cit. note 25 (1986), 46. 142 Fodor op. cit. note 87 (2003), 73. Schneider notes that Fodor's use of the term ‘pragmatism’ is ‘idiosyncratic’ and ‘unfortunate’ referring, not to the philosophical tradition of William James and John Dewey, but only to a theory of concept possession as a kind of ‘knowing how’ through abilities for recognition, classification and inference. See Schneider, S., The Language of Thought: A New Philosophical Direction (Cambridge, Mass.: MIT Press, 2011), 160 CrossRef | Google Scholar. 143 Cummins, R., The World in the Head (Oxford: Oxford University Press, 2010), 152–173 CrossRef | Google Scholar. 144 See Copenhaver op. cit. note 121 (2004), and van Cleve op. cit. note 104 (2015). 145 Wolterstorff, N., Thomas Reid and the Story of Epistemology (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 2001), 1 Google Scholar. 146 Lehrer, K., Thomas Reid (London: Routledge, 1989) Google Scholar; Putnam op. cit. note 119 (1994). 147 Strawson, G., ‘What's So Good About Reid?’, London Review of Books 22 (1990): 14–16 Google Scholar. 148 McGinn, C., The Character of Mind: An Introduction (Oxford: Oxford University Press, 1997), viii Google Scholar. 149 Rorty, R., ‘Blunder around for a while’, London Review of Books 13 (1991): 3–6 Google Scholar. 150 Pasnau op. cit. note 28 (1997), 294. I am grateful to Daniel Stoljar and David Chalmers for very helpful comments on an earlier version of this paper. Thanks also to Galen Strawson for helpful remarks on the themes of this paper.